Jump to content

Screech

Member
  • Content Count

    853
  • Joined

  • Last visited

  • Days Won

    4

Screech last won the day on February 18 2011

Screech had the most liked content!

Community Reputation

195 Excellent

About Screech

  • Rank
    Saved By the Bell
  • Birthday 07/14/1989

Profile Information

  • Name
    Aaron
  • School
    Portland State University
  • Location
    Portland, Oregon
  • Interests
    Putting of doing real work for as long as possible.

Contact Methods

  • AIM
    bitmapverse
  1. Your armchair psychology is stunning in its perspicacity. EDIT: LAWL AT BIG WERDZ
  2. Yeah, fuck that entire other tradition of philosophy! What's their DEAL?
  3. Ontology does not “come first,†but is negotiated pragmatically through the practice of coming up with conceptual schemes that map onto the world in useful ways. Ontological statements are no more or less privileged than factual ones and are subject to empirical falsification. To reject the facts at hand in order to look at ontology first misses the point entirely. Quine 1961 (William Van Orman, liberator of analytic philosophy from the philosophy of language and vanquisher of rationalism, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism†section V, http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html) [[CARD HAS BEEN EDITED FOR GENDERED LANGUGE]] The totality of our so-called knowledge or beliefs, from the most casual matters of geography and history to the profoundest laws of atomic physics or even of pure mathematics and logic, is a [human]-made fabric which impinges on experience only along the edges. Or, to change the figure, total science is like a field of force whose boundary conditions are experience. A conflict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the field. Truth values have to be redistributed over some of our statements. Re-evaluation of some statements entails re-evaluation of others, because of their logical interconnections -- the logical laws being in turn simply certain further statements of the system, certain further elements of the field. Having re-evaluated one statement we must re-evaluate some others, whether they be statements logically connected with the first or whether they be the statements of logical connections themselves. But the total field is so undetermined by its boundary conditions, experience, that there is much latitude of choice as to what statements to re-evaluate in the light of any single contrary experience. No particular experiences are linked with any particular statements in the interior of the field, except indirectly through considerations of equilibrium affecting the field as a whole. If this view is right, it is misleading to speak of the empirical content of an individual statement -- especially if it be a statement at all remote from the experiential periphery of the field. Furthermore it becomes folly to seek a boundary between synthetic statements, which hold contingently on experience, and analytic statements which hold come what may. Any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system. Even a statement very close to the periphery can be held true in the face of recalcitrant experience by pleading hallucination or by amending certain statements of the kind called logical laws. Conversely, by the same token, no statement is immune to revision. Revision even of the logical law of the excluded middle has been proposed as a means of simplifying quantum mechanics; and what difference is there in principle between such a shift and the shift whereby Kepler superseded Ptolemy, or Einstein Newton, or Darwin Aristotle? For vividness I have been speaking in terms of varying distances from a sensory periphery. Let me try now to clarify this notion without metaphor. Certain statements, though about physical objects and not sense experience, seem peculiarly germane to sense experience -- and in a selective way: some statements to some experiences, others to others. Such statements, especially germane to particular experiences, I picture as near the periphery. But in this relation of "germaneness" I envisage nothing more than a loose association reflecting the relative likelihood, in practice, of our choosing one statement rather than another for revision in the event of recalcitrant experience. For example, we can imagine recalcitrant experiences to which we would surely be inclined to accommodate our system by re-evaluating just the statement that there are brick houses on Elm Street, together with related statements on the same topic. We can imagine other recalcitrant experiences to which we would be inclined to accommodate our system by re-evaluating just the statement that there are no centaurs, along with kindred statements. A recalcitrant experience can, I have already urged, be accommodated by any of various alternative re-evaluations in various alternative quarters of the total system; but, in the cases which we are now imagining, our natural tendency to disturb the total system as little as possible would lead us to focus our revisions upon these specific statements concerning brick houses or centaurs. These statements are felt, therefore, to have a sharper empirical reference than highly theoretical statements of physics or logic or ontology. The latter statements may be thought of as relatively centrally located within the total network, meaning merely that little preferential connection with any particular sense data obtrudes itself. As an empiricist I continue to think of the conceptual scheme of science as a tool, ultimately, for predicting future experience in the light of past experience. Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries -- not by definition in terms of experience, but simply as irreducible posits18b comparable, epistemologically, to the gods of Homer. Let me interject that for my part I do, qua lay physicist, believe in physical objects and not in Homer's gods; and I consider it a scientific error to believe otherwise. But in point of epistemological footing the physical objects and the gods differ only in degree and not in kind. Both sorts of entities enter our conception only as cultural posits. The myth of physical objects is epistemologically superior to most in that it has proved more efficacious than other myths as a device for working a manageable structure into the flux of experience. Positing does not stop with macroscopic physical objects. Objects at the atomic level and beyond are posited to make the laws of macroscopic objects, and ultimately the laws of experience, simpler and more manageable; and we need not expect or demand full definition of atomic and subatomic entities in terms of macroscopic ones, any more than definition of macroscopic things in terms of sense data. Science is a continuation of common sense, and it continues the common-sense expedient of swelling ontology to simplify theory. Physical objects, small and large, are not the only posits. Forces are another example; and indeed we are told nowadays that the boundary between energy and matter is obsolete. Moreover, the abstract entities which are the substance of mathematics -- ultimately classes and classes of classes and so on up -- are another posit in the same spirit. Epistemologically these are myths on the same footing with physical objects and gods, neither better nor worse except for differences in the degree to which they expedite our dealings with sense experiences. The over-all algebra of rational and irrational numbers is underdetermined by the algebra of rational numbers, but is smoother and more convenient; and it includes the algebra of rational numbers as a jagged or gerrymandered part.19b Total science, mathematical and natural and human, is similarly but more extremely underdetermined by experience. The edge of the system must be kept squared with experience; the rest, with all its elaborate myths or fictions, has as its objective the simplicity of laws. Ontological questions, under this view, are on a par with questions of natural science.20b Consider the question whether to countenance classes as entities. This, as I have argued elsewhere,10a21b is the question whether to quantify with respect to variables which take classes as values. Now Carnap ["Empiricism, semantics, and ontology," Revue internationale de philosophie 4 (1950), 20-40.] has maintained11a that this is a question not of matters of fact but of choosing a convenient language form, a convenient conceptual scheme or framework for science. With this I agree, but only on the proviso that the same be conceded regarding scientific hypotheses generally. Carnap has recognized12a that he is able to preserve a double standard for ontological questions and scientific hypotheses only by assuming an absolute distinction between the analytic and the synthetic; and I need not say again that this is a distinction which I reject. 22b The issue over there being classes seems more a question of convenient conceptual scheme; the issue over there being centaurs, or brick houses on Elm Street, seems more a question of fact. But I have been urging that this difference is only one of degree, and that it turns upon our vaguely pragmatic inclination to adjust one strand of the fabric of science rather than another in accommodating some particular recalcitrant experience. Conservatism figures in such choices, and so does the quest or simplicity. Carnap, Lewis, and others take a pragmatic stand on the question of choosing between language forms, scientific [and] frameworks; but their pragmatism leaves off at the imagined boundary between the analytic and the synthetic. In repudiating such a boundary I espouse a more thorough pragmatism. Each [person] is given a scientific heritage plus a continuing barrage of sensory stimulation; and the considerations which guide [them] in warping [their] scientific heritage to fit [their] continuing sensory promptings are, where rational, pragmatic. EDIT: Fixed Quine's name.
  4. This thread is a perfect mirror of the great macrocosm of Christian apologetics writ small. That is to say, it's an endless, groundless churn of question-begging and abject nonsense, which avoids refutation because of its continuous shifting of the topic and goalposts.
  5. My point was not that you can't make inferences about God's motives but that if you do, you can't prevent me from doing so (say, by making a rhetorical move that God's motives are inscrutable). So you can't solve the problem of evil: like why would God allow evil that humans didn't cause to exist? Or if freedom is going to cause so much suffering, why give us free will?
  6. The argument that choice is morally important is question-begging because it presumes any benevolent god would prefer freedom to all other human virtues. If the mind of god is unknowable to the point where it is unfathomable why they would create the would as it currently is, you're exercising bad faith when you then appeal to an external value to claim that that is the basis of god's inscrutable value judgment. Either we can know the mind of god, in which case I can present arguments that this is not the best of all possible worlds (and you haven't solved the problem of evil), or we can't, in which case you can't appeal to god's value judgment about "freedom" (and you haven't solved the problem of evil). Love your line, by the way, retired. "God-shaped whole," eh. So... altruism is favored by evolution? (I literally brought this up in the fourth post in the thread, I'm more than comfortable with this conclusion) So, in some cases, is social parasitism.
  7. I'm not getting into the "nature of divine morality" debate, it's dumb. But just to follow your argument to the logical conclusion here, doesn't that imply that God's plan for the universe cannot be fixed by external standards of morality, because no such standards exist? So in what sense can God be called "omnibenevolent"? And what other criteria might an omnipotent and omniscient deity use to construct a plan for the world?
  8. That's if you assume there are three possible outcomes (good, evil, neutral). I would argue there are an infinite number of possible outcomes on a spectrum from perfectly good to perfectly evil, and therefore the possibility of god being perfectly good is lim(x->infinity)1/x = 0.
  9. Screech

    The Oscars

    I... Er... Well... Vacuous?
  10. Screech

    The Oscars

    Thanks, that's... descriptive.
  11. Screech

    The Oscars

    Don't claim that Inception is unoriginal or McNinja will give you an infraction!
  12. Screech

    The Oscars

    Whether or not King's Speech deserved Best Picture, Colin Firth's performance was mindbogglingly good and easily deserving of Best Male Actor.
  13. Actually, that's a good point. I've definitely heard "uniqueness overwhelms the link" much more commonly and I'm pretty sure I meant that when I said "brink overwhelms the link" (UQ is too strong, the link isn't sufficient to get us there). On your reading, (Brink is too strong, so link will be triggered regardless) I would basically classify it as a non-unique. Sorry for the confusion.
  14. Uniqueness overwhelms the link and brink overwhelms the link are equivalent in my taxonomy, unless there's some distinction I'm missing.
×
×
  • Create New...